God, Analogy, and the Metaphysics of Participation

by Robert Fortuin

There’s an interesting post over at Tom Belt’s Open Orthodoxy blog—“Lost in Translation” (part 1 and part 2)—which developed into a conversation about a conversation. The post and the subsequent comments concern a topic of great importance. It is difficult to respond in a comment section beyond a few hastily put together sentences (and without the column width of replies to narrow to an inch—why? are we out of space??) so I thought it would be better to create a slightly more substantial contribution here (thank you Fr Kimel!). Let me briefly summarize the problematic of “Lost in Translation.”

Tom’s post presents a dialogue between himself and interlocutor “Webster” (who subse­quently outed himself as Jeff, ha!) about what precisely is conveyed when we speak about God. How does theological language capture meaning? Can we claim to know anything at all about God, and if we can, then how do we come about such knowledge? The problem that confronts us is that the God of theism classically conceived is not an ordinary subject, a discrete object which can be defined, measured, conceptualized. God cannot be classified to belong to any genera. Yet to truly communicate, for words to convey meaning and value, we need to do just this—to define, measure, and compare, and thereby to communicate mean­ing and value. Jeff’s complaint is that analogy makes meaning so slippery that no explaining power is left in the words Tom uses to explicate meaning in regards to God. God “cares about” and “loves” people, but evidently not in the way we are ordinarily use these words (hence Tom’s use of quotation marks). But what then DO these words mean then? The objection Jeff raises strikes at the heart of analogy’s claim as to its ability to establish true knowledge about God. No trivial matter.

A secondary issue was raised by Tom as to how one goes about establishing meaning by way of analogy. Asks Tom, “What are the actual steps one takes to establish (for us creatures) the meaning of a term like “person” or “love” within a larger infinite distance?” The chief prob­lem here is the issue of the ‘always larger dissimilarity’ by which any likeness is to be held in check. To state it in the words of the Fourth Lateran Council, “between creator and creature there can be noted no similarity so great that a greater dissimilarity cannot be seen between them.” This appears to denote that the greater (infinite no less!) unlikeness cancels out any notion of likeness. Silence is the only appropriate stance—under the immense weight of the infinite interval of dissimilarity our ability to affirm cataphatically has collapsed to ruin. Was this the beginning of an incipient nihilism, a consequence of what the likes of Aquinas and the bishops of the Lateran council meant by analogy?

Such a conclusion would only hold if the doctrine of analogy is taken out of its metaphysical context, and if analogy is understood to be primarily a method to provide us with knowledge about God. As important as theological language theory may be (and it is, don’t get me wrong), it is far too often imagined to be a discipline which creates its own picture of reality. But it makes a lot more sense to consider language as dependent upon and proceeding from metaphysics: that is to say that the question of the possibility of meaning depends in large on the nature of reality envisioned. Theological language of analogical predication can only function correctly insofar it is considered in the light of metaphysics, in particular a meta­physics of participation.

To that end here are few of the main tenets of the metaphysic of participation that must be brought to bear in any consideration of analogy, and in order to understand how and why analogy functions as a pillar of classical theism. Time does not permit to develop supporting arguments, so these will be presented in the form of assertions:

  • Effect resembles its cause. The effect bears real similarity to its cause. The resemblance is real, however present in the creature proper to its mode as contingent, derivative, and finite. The created is like its creator, and not conversely.
  • Existence and essence coincide in God who is self-existing and self-sufficient. Because existence and essence are identical in God, the divine perfections are not possessed. God does not have love, he is love.
  • By way of perfections observed in creation (however fragmented and limited), perfections can be affirmed of God.
  • While finite beings have real perfections in limited ways, the perfections exist super-eminently (formerly and eminently) in God. The presence of the perfections in creation, however real, are dissimilar to the perfections affirmed in God according to the mode they are attributed. The dissimilarity is in the mode, or manner, by which perfections are attributed, proper to God and creature respectively. This is the res/modus distinction.
  • Analogy functions not as a way to provide knowledge, but as a way to describe how we have the knowledge already apprehended. To address Jeff’s concern about the meaning of words in analogous predication, we can affirm that God is (super eminently) love by the love observed in the creature.
  • The analogy is an ontological analogy, an analogy of being, and not merely nor primarily a linguistic device.
  • The analogization consists in the difference of being between God and creature, not between God and creature under a shared category of being. This is, in short, the meaning of the difference between Being and beings.

Tom proposes to begin with a univocal meaning of ‘love’ and then to qualify it by saying the essential meaning we associate with the term is infinitely, perfectly, transcendentally actual in God. My reply is that we begin with love not understood univocally (as both Tom and Jeff suggest) but analogously as follows: love as we know it is truly similar to God’s love (effect resembles its cause) but it is dissimilar in the manner it is attributed to God and to us (the res/modus distinction). For to God love is attributed super-eminently: God does not participate in nor acquire love—God is love. Yet it remains that the love we know is like God’s love (literally so, Aquinas posits); however, we possess love by participation in God: contingently, derivatively and in measure and degree. While perfections obtain to God literally, they are applied analogously rather than univocally due to the modal disjunction between God and creation. The distinction between the perfec­tion attributed and the manner the perfection is attributed (perfectio significata vs modus significandi) proper to God and creature respectively, means that the dissimilarity does not cancel out the similarity. The likeness of the res signified persists in the mode it is signified. In this way of analogy classic theism stays clear of the equivocation suggested by John Stuart Mill, “To say that God’s goodness may be different in kind from man’s goodness, what is it but saying, with a slight change of phraseology, that God may possibly not be good?”

God’s act of being is the plentitude of the good fully actualized, a foretaste of which we encounter in the good of creation. Creation’s teleos (perfection) is its perfection in the Good.

This entry was posted in Robert Fortuin and tagged , , , , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

20 Responses to God, Analogy, and the Metaphysics of Participation

  1. brian says:

    Outstanding, Robert. The univocal tendency which dominates in the analytic tradition tends to be suspicious of equivocity, let alone analogy. I think it lacks an intuition of the hyperbolics of being. Hence, it thinks any breakdown of univocity as opening the gates to a nihilist abandon.

    Like

    • Robert Fortuin says:

      Thank you Brian. What in your estimation can be done to assuage this suspicion? The way I see it is that there is a fundamental disagreement about the nature of reality (as you say, “the hyperbolics of being”) which in turn affects language theory – the function of language, its limits and conditions, how and why it signifies meaning, and so forth. Every now and then I wonder if a fruitful conversation between analogismoi and analitikoi is even a possibility. Is there common ground?

      Like

      • brian says:

        I don’t have an answer, Robert. The problem exceeds the strong difference in sensibility between say, the Anglo-American analytic/pragmatic proclivities and Continental philosophy. Eric Voegelin opined that we no longer had enough common ground to make a work like Aquinas’ Summa contra Gentiles possible. And I have applauded David C. Schindler’s recent Freedom from Reality which articulates how modern notions of freedom and autonomy give moral cover to a general flight from reality. While one might think that a kind of minimalist objectivism inherent in the project of science and in univocal attempts to pin down the truth of things would act as a break on delusion, the fact that qualia are subsumed into pure subjectivism militates against any significant realist counter to the trajectory towards solipsistic autism that is the logical consequence of modernist assumptions. Balthasar adverted early on to the importance of beauty, because beauty is the transcendental of the radiance of being. Beauty cannot be commanded. To experience beauty is to recognize the “oversaturated” quality of being that carries meaning in excess of all our methodological and procedural efforts at control and logical containment. So, in the end, there has to be a reverence for being that is probably the fruit of a praxis far from what our culture is encouraging or even acknowledging as licit. There is frequently deep alienation between one sort and another, so that many years ago C.P. Snow wrote of the two cultures, emphasizing an abyssal separation between the arts and the sciences. This is the result of many erroneous judgments and a figure like Goethe pointed the way towards a more unified consciousness, but how one can initiate a serious rapproachment between advocates of starkly drawn alternatives is hard to imagine.

        Liked by 1 person

        • Robert Fortuin says:

          It is interesting you mention beauty Brian – before I read your reply to me, in my response to Vaska, I used beauty as well. Of the transcendentals beauty exemplifies the excess, and the inability to fully capture it. Here the notion of participation I find so very useful, as in participation we don’t fully possess it (rather we are possessed by it, we might say), while we share truly it is only in degree and over time. Here of course comes to the foreground the sharp contrast between the fragmented, accidental joining of essence and existence on the hand, and the full actuality of essence and existence in perfect coincidence, on the other hand.

          Interestingly it is actuality unfulfilled, a potential undetermined, which underwrites the notion of unending progress toward transcendental excess, epektasis, which we find in Gregory of Nyssa.

          Liked by 1 person

  2. Vaska says:

    “But it makes a lot more sense to consider language as dependent upon and proceeding from metaphysics: that is to say that the question of the possibility of meaning depends in large on the nature of reality envisioned. ”

    With all due respect, this literally doesn’t make sense, i.e. doesn’t hold. No metaphysics is prior to the language which describes, delineates, and annunciates it. The reality envisioned by any metaphysics comes into being as a metaphysics, as something we can formulate and articulate and have conversations about, only through the language used to formulate and articulate it. What we can know about God may transcend it (as it does in the experience of Christian mystics, for example), but what we can say about God is dependent on language.

    Like

    • brian says:

      That’s fine. I agree that one cannot properly separate a “prior” metaphysics from language, but one still has to address the primal experience of wonder or perhaps later perplexity that explicitly or tacitly acknowledges what is in excess of language. Insofar as language is thought as confined to what is determinately known, one will embrace a reductionist metaphysics. I think Robert is trying to keep open the connection between metaphysics and elemental astonishment. Think of the difference between how Hamann conceived language and his Enlightenment counterparts.

      Liked by 1 person

      • Grant says:

        I’m not really qualified to give any truly informed opinion on these matters (so that has to be borne in mind with anything I say), but II would agree with you Brian. Language of all kinds are expressions and communication of consciousness, an articulation of our consciousness, being and relation to being (as well as other beings). Language of all kinds (including mathematics, music, arts and so on) is founded on and flows from that experience, primal awareness, wonder and insight into existence within and around us, and thus reaches beyond itself to transcendent Being beyond in everything.

        I think that that elemental wonder, joy and experience of being (and however confused) Being beyond that is central to us in our conscious existence, is inherently to live and exist metaphysics as it were, and that language flows from this relational experience of our very nature as embedded and embodied conscious finite beings in relation to other finite beings, orientated, participating and reaching towards infinite Being Himself (but perhaps I’m presuming a conclusion that those of an analytical and similar view are disputing).

        Liked by 2 people

    • Robert Fortuin says:

      Vaska,

      What I am leaning against is meaning (and therefore language) which is thought to be established primarily or even merely on a horizontal level giving way to an univocal value system. So for example, I consider beauty not merely an ideal but a transcendental source – for beauty is a metaphysical reality. It is this consideration of the transcendental upon which meaning first and finally rests. Our thoughts and words – our finitude really – cannot exhaust the metaphysical reality and thus always fall short; it is therefore a language univocally conceived that I consider to be categorically improper to its task to give expression to the excess which it encounters. Hence a metaphysics of participation and analogy.

      Does that clarify?

      Like

  3. Julian says:

    Robert,

    I am very much of a novice in these matters, so I’m hoping you can help me out with something I’ve been wondering about. When I think about something like beauty (eg. this is a beautiful flower) it seems to be something my mind projects on to the world. Beauty seems to be something that is dependent on mind, so as a theist I would say that beauty is something God projects on the world.
    However, from what I’ve read from people like Ed. Fieser (and maybe the Orthodox have a different view on this) beauty is not projected on to the world, by either me or God, but is rather inherent within it. The problem this causes for me is that I would like to say that Beauty is dependent on God, and it seems incomprehensible to think of Beauty without recourse to consciousness (either my own or God’s) So what does it mean to say Beutey is WITHIN things, or that it is a transcendent reality? How can I conceptualize this?

    I hope my question isn’t too muddled for you to answer.

    Thanks.

    Like

  4. brian says:

    Julian,

    WIlliam Desmond talks about the “between” quality of metaphysics — metaxological derived from the Greek metaxu (or metaxy) for in-between. You might want to peruse the third post in this thread where I broach the danger of solipsistic autism in certain notions of subjectivity. What needs to be avoided is a sharp dualism where one has a conscious subjective center on one side and normally a kind of inert objectivity on the other. Such a view is more Cartesian than biblical. If beauty is the radiance of being, then created being communicates its own essence, ultimately its own unique singularity. If you want to locate beauty purely in the perceptor, you are taking away the integrity of created being. Theologically, one is approaching a kind of occasionalism whereby finite being is coopted into divine action. There would then be no true drama between God and creation, nor would creation communicate its own irreplaceable “thisness.” It is true that creatures “participate” in Being. There is a divine root, an agapeic giftedness that is the dynamic, continuing intimacy between God and creature. In this sense, finite beauty is a splendor that points back to TriUne Beauty, but it does not diminish the genuine beauty of integral creaturely being. Further, one can admit that if creaturely being is communicative, it requires the perceptive other, for a message must be heard and cherished in order to be complete. So, it is not wrong to anticipate the need for an “other” to “complete the circuit,” but it is wrong to locate the entirety of beauty in one side or the other. C. S. Lewis warned against thinking beauty was only “in the subject” in his prescient The Abolition of Man. The example he gives is of a modern person looking at a waterfall and thinking “I am now having sublime feelings” rather than thinking the waterfall itself was sublime. In short, reality is always “in between” as a dynamic and dramatic act that happens in the event of meeting between creatures and ultimately between creatures and God.

    Liked by 2 people

  5. Julian says:

    Thanks Brian, what you say about in betweenness makes me think of Logos, is that barking up the right tree?

    Like

    • brian says:

      Metaxological thinking is too complex to be reduced to any simple formulation. Hence, Desmond has devoted thousands of pages to trying to articulate its meaning and nuances. Logos just by itself is equivocal. It could mean many things. For instance, it could suggest something like Maximus the Confessor’s notion that all creaturely logoi have their source in the Divine Logos. I’m certainly not going to argue against that, but the drama of the metaxy requires a broader conceptual range. My sense is that your tendency, Julian, is to emphasize the divine pole. Transcendence is both “beyond” and “within” or “amidst.” Reverent attention to the creaturely pole is part of the necessary equation. Father Kimel’s newest post today (a Desmond quote) is relevant as demonstrating the kind of multi-layered complexity of awareness and interpretation that is required.

      Like

      • Julian says:

        Brian, can you think of any introductory books, articles ect. for getting into this?

        Like

        • Fr Aidan Kimel says:

          Julian, you know not what you ask! 😀 😀 😀

          Liked by 1 person

        • brian says:

          Julian, Christopher Ben Simpson has edited a William Desmond Reader that gives a fairly brief representative exposition of his thought. I think Perplexity and Ultimacy and Philosophy and Its Others are reasonable choices as works to begin with. There’s a kind of big trilogy that you would want to work up to (Being and the Between, Ethics and the Between, God and the Between.)

          Liked by 1 person

          • Julian says:

            Why are you suggesting Desmond in particular? I was thinking I would start with David Bentley Hart’s The experience of God, he seems to be dealing with the questions I’m trying to answer. Would that be a decent place to start in your estimation?

            Like

  6. brian says:

    Julian,

    I began by attempting to answer your question about beauty, God, and finite being. Desmond was brought in as a strong metaphysical understanding that opposes various unbalanced notions of subjectivity. After that, I have just been trying to answer your further inquiries. Hart’s book has many excellent qualities. It is largely devoted to elucidating a proper sense of divine transcendence. Many atheists tacitly acknowledged the power of the argument by peevishly claiming the text was an exercise in dissimulation whereby an indefensible biblical God was replaced by an anodyne god of metaphysics. By this tendentious interpretation, they willfully or ignorantly missed the point. Rather than separation, a proper metaphysics is ultimately derivative of revelation and also conducive to a better grasp of the biblical God. While moderns understand transcendence as creating a dualist opposition to the finite and immanent, divine transcendence is both “beyond” and “within,” founding an unimaginable intimacy with creation. In short, Hart demonstrates that any reading of scripture that would equate God with a mere supreme being or a heroicized finite sense of person is an idol based on an implicit faulty metaphysics. By all means, follow the eros of your soul. The Experience of God is certainly a wise book.

    Like

    • Robert Fortuin says:

      The problem with Hart and Desmond is that both assume the reader has a working understanding of philosophy and metaphysics, and without such the arguments and positions put forth easily lead to misunderstanding.

      Like

  7. brian says:

    Julian, I think you might benefit from Norris Clarke’s Person and Being. His introduction to metaphysics, The One and the Many, is also about as accessible as that kind of book can be. I generally recommend Josef Pieper, though it appears many of his works have gone out of print if the price on Amazon is any indication.

    Liked by 1 person

Comments are closed.