The Naiveté of Naïve Universalism

The naïve construal of universal salvation (“the view that upon death all persons are instantly transformed by God in such a way that they fully desire communion with God and are thus fit for enjoying the beatific vision forever”1) suffers, argues Michael J. Murray, from two critical weaknesses.

First, naïve universalism renders our experience of evil gratuitous. Evils are gratuitous, Murray explains, if God permits them to impact our lives yet from them does not bring about an intrinsic good that outweighs the sufferings, burdens, and privations they impose:

On the NU picture, all human beings end up in perfect communion with God, enjoying the beatific vision forever. This entails, however, that one’s fate in eternity is entirely independent of the individual choices a person makes and the beliefs a person adopts in the earthly phase of their existence. Thus, the evils that one experiences in the earthly life are gratuitous. Why, one is led to wonder, would God put us through such a pointless exercise, an exercise filled with much misery, suffering, and travail, only in the end to invest the experience with no ultimate consequences or significance?2

If our beliefs, choices, and actions do not determine our eschatological destiny, if nothing about our temporal existence is necessary to the securing of our final good, then what the heck is the point of the afflictions and evils we endure? And that is the point—they have no point. If all will be saved in instantaneous transformation, then our present struggles and sufferings are rendered meaningless; they have no salvific purpose. Our creation into this fallen world thus becomes an act of divine cruelty. Surely the Almighty could have skipped the mortal coil bit and jumped right to glory:3

Why would God prefer to have us spend our first seventy or so years of existence in this earthly phase, enjoying a measure of intrinsic good but with the accompanying evil required to secure it, rather than positioning us in such a way that these years are spent in perfect communion with Him in heaven? After all, any earthly goods obtained would pale in comparison with the goods achieved by spending those years in this way.4

Second, naïve universalism denies the autonomy of human beings. As Murray defines the term, autonomy designates not just the freedom of the individual to make choices but the ability to affect one’s world through one’s free actions:

It is a commonplace among theists responding to the problem of evil that appeal be made to creaturely freedom. Since, creatures are free (in the libertarian sense) they have the power to go wrong, and God cannot de-activate this power without de-activating the creature’s freedom. Furthermore, it is commonly held that the existence of these free creatures justifies the resultant moral evil, since a world with free creatures is on balance better because the existence of such creatures permits the possibility of moral goods. But, as many have noted, it is not mere “freedom of choice” that the theist is after with such theodicies. What the theist really needs is a freedom of choosing that is expressed in actions that influence the course of events in the world. Thus, in addition to the ability to choose in the absence of determinism, the libertarian theist also wants choices that result in significant change in the local environment. Let us call this latter feature “autonomy” to distinguish it from the mere “freedom of choice” often emphasized by libertarians. Thus, a world with “autonomous” creatures is a world where creatures are not only allowed to make evil choices, but choices which issue in evil acts and have evil consequences. A world with agents who can choose freely but are unable to act autonomously would be a world filled with freely choosing brains-in-vats. While free choosing might go on, the choices would never have expression in or impact on the local environment, whether good or evil.5

Naïve universalism denies personal autonomy. While it affirms libertarian choosing, it also imposes a single eschatological outcome for all human beings. In this life we are free to cultivate a depraved character, but in the eschaton, no one will have a depraved character. All our hard work in becoming evil will have been for nothing. It’s like going through the drive-thru at MacDonalds. We are free to order any items on the menu we want—hamburger, french fries, milkshake, whatever—but no matter what we order, the attendant always gives us a Big Mac. So with universalism. No matter whether we have lived a virtuous or sinful life, no matter how wickedly we have behaved, no matter what kind of persons we have become, when we die God will make us holy and loving people, with or without our consent. “While free choosing may go on in the universalist’s world,” remarks Murray, “it is a free choosing that is without autonomy, since one is transformed into a lover of God, whether one chooses to be such or not.”6 Protest as we might, the game is rigged. The Creator doesn’t ask our permission to save us; he just does it. Love wins—always. I’m sure you feel as violated as I do.

The theodicean question remains: If God is able to instantaneously change us into immortal persons fit for heaven apart from our willing (brains-in-vats), why does he place us in a world of gratuitous evil, suffering, and death?7

Is naïve universalism as naïve and flawed as Michael Murray presents it? I personally do not find his article convincing, but others will disagree. Over two millennia, the overwhelming majority of universalists have preferred, and continue to prefer, a purgatorial model. This model appears to escape Murray’s strictures. We will examine universalist purgatory when I return to my review of Once Loved Always Loved.

 

Footnotes

[1] Michael J. Murray, “Three Versions of Universalism,” Faith and Philosophy, 16 (1999): 56. In the 19th century, Hosea Ballou advanced a universalist position that appears to qualify as naïve universalism. It was very popular in American universalist circles for several decades but eventually lost out to restorationist construals. See “Death and Glory: The Ultra-Universalism of Hosea Ballou.”

[2] Ibid., 56. “An evil E is nongratuitous if, and only if, (a) there exists some outweighing intrinsic good G such that it was not within God’s power to achieve G without either permitting E or permitting some other evil at least as bad as E and (b) there is not some further intrinsic good G*, which is both exclusive of G and greater than G, which could have been secured without permitting E or some other evil at least as bad as E.” Ibid.

[3] Roberto De La Noval raises this concern in his review of That All Shall Be Saved: “Universalism: The Only Theodicy?” See David Bentley Hart’s response: “Theodicy and Apokatastasis.” Also: Thomas Talbott, “Universalism and the Supposed Oddity of Our Earthly Life,” Faith and Philosophy 18 (2001): 102-109.

[4] Murray, 57.

[5] Ibid., 58.

[6] Ibid., 59.

[7] For a critique of Murray’s argument, see Daniel Howard-Snyder, “In Defense of Naïve Universalism,” Faith and Philosophy, 20 (2003): 345-363. Also see Andrew Hronich, Once Loved Always Loved (2023), chap. 7.

This entry was posted in Universalism and Eschatology and tagged , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

12 Responses to The Naiveté of Naïve Universalism

  1. Robin of Lilyfield says:

    First of all, to state that a person is instantly saved is inaccurate. Not only did this person live their duration of life on earth, but all of the conditions that made that life possible (their parents, their ancestors, the earth, the universe) was a very slowly developing process evolving over billions of years. It is hardly an instantaneous event. And also, we must remember that it is not simply human beings that are saved, but all of creation, every blade of grass—the entire universe. 

    Moreover, it would seem to me that the arguments against naive universalism are essentially the same arguments against universalism in general. 

    The question, “If everyone is saved instantly upon death, why live a virtuous life?” does not differ from “If everyone is saved, why live a virtuous life?”

    And the answer is the same in both cases. 

    I would also add that if you are living in a particular way of life in order to gain heaven and/or avoid a hell of any duration, then you are not living a virtuous life. 

    In terms of answering the first question—regarding the purpose of this world with all of its struggle—it may be that earthly experience is preparing us in ways that are not overtly apparent at this point. It may be that it is our intimate experience with the immense limitation of this mode of existence that is necessary prerequisite for the subsequent expansion of being that is to come.

    Liked by 1 person

  2. Shaun Thomas-Arnold says:

    On the first point, I would argue the opposite. If ECT is true, then we learn nothing from either the good or evil we do in this life, all of it hinges on whether we choose to accept God ourselves, whether or not it is for selfish reasons. It also seems to ignore the idea that people that have committed terrible acts have repented at the ends of their lives. Does their repentance not lead to salvation?

    As Robin comments, Murray seems to think the idea of universalism is that God snaps his fingers and everyone is suddenly a saint. When in reality, based on Scripture, God leads us to repentance. Helps us to learn from our mistakes, forgives us our failures and—rather than condemn us for failing within a world we neither created nor asked to exist within—ultimately turns them to victories so that his will and purpose may redeem his own creation.

    Murray’s ideals, like all of ECT, put the onus on the human. It makes the human the one able to carry out God’s will or else thwart it. The doctrine is all rather self-centered and I honestly don’t see where it leaves room for the redemption; certainly not for God’s presence and guidance from finding faith (and even this is a gift) to growing in sanctification.

    Liked by 1 person

    • Fr Aidan Kimel says:

      Robin and Shaun, I encourage you to read Murphy’s article. You will discover that “naive universalism” is a construct he has designed for the purpose of analysis and discussion. In fact, he doesn’t think anyone has seriously advocated it. He happens to be wrong about that, as I show in my article on Hosea Ballou, but that is by the by.

      Liked by 1 person

      • Shaun Thomas-Arnold says:

        I see, thank you for the correction. Though I have seen others, in attacking universalism, use these same misconstrued talking points. The Gospel Coalitions refutation of CU seems to go out of its way to make false assumptions and argue for misconceptions that no reasonable, educated universalist is actually arguing. Considering the number of books that have been published on the topic over the past two decades, I can only assume it’s on purpose.

        Liked by 1 person

  3. Iainlovejoy says:

    It seems to me the problem is with the entire concept of “instant” change. “Instant” implies a discontinuity, where the old ceases to exist in its current form and a new essentially different thing replaces it. If in going from “unsaved” me to “saved” me I do not traverse and experience all the intermediate stages of that transformation then it seems to me that the new “saved” me would not be me at all but a new being recycling some of the parts left over from when the original unsaved me was annihilated and destroyed.

    It occurs to me that the difference between naïve universalism and the idea of universal purgatory (which Fr Aiden is covering next) lies not in the concept of all universally being transformed and perfected on death, on which they are in essential agreement, but in their understanding of what it may be like to experience being changed in this way.

    Liked by 1 person

    • Fr Aidan Kimel says:

      Iain, I question whether “instant” transformation implies discontinuity of identity. Imagine this scenario: I fall asleep and when I awake I discover that I no longer desire ____. I don’t know why this change has occurred. Am I a different person? I don’t think so. My previous memories remain intact, which of course is why I notice the change.

      Now expand the illustration. I die and “awaken” into my resurrection life. I immediately note that I am now surrounded by the company of heaven and my soul is filled with the presence and love of God. My desires have been healed and reordered. I now want to know God more than anything. I have fallen in love with my Creator. Is my heavenly identity radically discontinuous with my historical identity? I wouldn’t think so. My previous memories remain intact. Even though I cannot explain the change, I recognize that something has happened to me. I may be different, but I am still the same me.

      Liked by 1 person

      • Gios says:

        Btw, I think that some form of discontinuity is part of the grammar of many churches. Like when in Baptism many christians say that we die so as to be reborn in Christ, or, more generally, when we convert and we are transfigured. I don’t think it would be inappropriate to say that we die and are reborn also as a result of a good and true confession. It would be interesting to better understand this problem of discontinuity…

        Liked by 1 person

      • Robert Fortuin says:

        I surmise notions of time, the instant and the prolonged stretch, all are equally problematic and ultimately without meaning. Really what is it that we are trying to accomplish by projecting time onto eternity? We want to account for change such as repentance or growth and development, but this takes time; time is needed for transformation from this to that, for one instance to change to another instance. Does this hold in eternity, does it really need the lapse of time for change to occur? We can’t imagine change without time, that’s the root of the problem. We need to resist quantifying eternity, smuggling time to account for change. Easier said thatn done. Can we imagine a state of being in which the instant and the eternal perfectly coincide, the moment of time collapsing into the infinite, time existing in and fulfilled by the timeless? Time that itself is transformed from the limitation of the momentary ‘now’ and the momentary ‘here’ to a complete present ‘containing’ past and future, stasis and change? It seems to me we have to stretch our imagination to account for this. Somehow.

        Liked by 1 person

        • Fr Aidan Kimel says:

          But there may be a radical difference between the eternity of the transcendent God and the eternity of resurrected human beings. Following Paul Griffiths, I tend to think that the latter enjoy a transfigured temporality. The same may also apply to angels.

          Liked by 1 person

      • Iainlovejoy says:

        The scenario you outline sounds awfully like someone who has suffered a stroke or some kind of brain damage. Our desires are not discrete, independent things but products of our nature and personality. The other problem is that sin is always seen as a lack of something or something missing or distorted in ourselves, rather than an excisable add-on to be surgically removed. That being said, if our remaining sin is a residual habit or peripheral to our core being perhaps we can indeed simply be cured of it in this way, which would be nice. I think my point still stands though in relation to those for whom perceive their sin as core to their being and are desperate to cling to it, and would desperately want it back if it were lost. I think if we are in such a state then there would have to be more to a cure, and the process may well have to be a necessarily painful one, if only because our resistance and desire not to be cured make it so.

        Like

  4. Joe says:

    I think God loves us, regardless of whether we love Him in return, yet I also wonder if at some point, if we continue to reject Him, He gives us our way….I’m probably not adding much to this erudite conversation. I think that God, after a while, says “Well, ok, have it your way…” not exactly McDonalds – more like Burger King.

    Like

  5. Colin Gallagher says:

    thanks for sharing all of theses

    Liked by 2 people

Leave a comment